Hi Sarah,
Thanks for the questions! Let me start by talking about the contrapositive first. The goal is ultimately for you to see contrapositives in an automatic, near-instant manner. It should eventually be the case where when you see a statement like A
B, in your mind you not only see that, but the contrapositive (
B A) as well. This is because when you have a conditional statement, there is always a contrapositive (CP). So, seeing a statement and its CP should go hand-in-hand. Now, do you need to write out each CP also? My answer is no. I only write out unusual contrapositives. the rule of thumb should be to write it out when you feel that doing so will help you. So, statements like A
B aren't going to cause me to write out the CP. Something like A + B
C or D would cause me to write it out. I know from the other question you posted that contrapositives are giving you some trouble, so this is a point I really want to make sure you are comfortable with, because it will help eliminate a set of problems you have. So, let me know if the above makes sense, and do not hesitate at all to ask me questions about ti if something isn't entirely clear there
Ok, that said, let's move on to the two inferences you asked about:
- The inference resulting from the combination of rules 1 + 3
Rule #1: B D
Rule #3: C D
Since D is common to both rules, we can combine them into a chain: C D B (B D is reversible, so I can flip it around and it works exactly the same). This "X Y Z" form is a classic inference-generating form, and always results in an inference where the two terms at the ends of the chain cannot go together, which in this specific case is C B. Why does this happen? It's discussed on pages 244-245, and page 264. The gist is that C requires D, but D doesn't like B. So, whenever you have C you must have D, but that knocks out B. The result is that C and B can never go together.
The inference resulting from the combination of 1 + 4
Rule #1: B D
Rule #4: G B
This is the same basic inference as 1+3 above, so I'll use the same basic analysis: since B is common to both rules, we can combine them into a chain: G B D. This results in an inference where the two terms at the ends of the chain cannot go together: G D. The gist is that G requires B, but B doesn't like D. So, whenever you have G you must have B, but that knocks out D. The result is that G and D can never go together.
Please let me know if that helps. Both of your inference questions come from the same exact form, and its a form you see a lot on the LSAT. It's also one of the two most frequently appearing inference chains (the other is A
B
C), so we want to make sure you have this one locked down because you'll see it again. And again. And again
Thanks!