- Sun Jan 20, 2013 12:00 am
#36287
Complete Question Explanation
Justify the Conclusion—SN. The correct answer choice is (C)
The argument can be viewed as follows:
Premise: For each action we perform, we can know only some of its consequences.
Conclusion: Thus the view that in no situation can we know what action is morally right
would be true if an action’s being morally right were the same as the action’s
having the best consequences.
This stimulus looks somewhat intimidating, but in laymen’s terms, the argument really means the
following:
When you do something, there are some consequences that you cannot know about. So, if
being morally right is the same as knowing the best consequences, then there is no way to
know if an action is morally right.
The question asks you to Justify the Conclusion, so seek an answer that forces the conclusion
to follow from the premises. In the argument, the author makes a leap between not knowing all
the consequences and not knowing the best consequences, so you should look for an answer that
connects those two ideas (remember, morally right requires knowing the best consequences, yet we
can’t know the best consequences because we can’t know all the consequences).
Mechanistically speaking, the conclusion contains the new idea of “best consequences,” so look for
an answer that addresses that new element.
Answer choice (A): The stimulus concerns whether we can prove actions morally right, and being
able to prove some of them wrong does not help decide whether some can be proven right.
Answer choice (B): The conclusion attempts to prove that we cannot know that a situation is morally
right if morally right is the same as having the best consequences. This answer, which states that on
occasion we can know what is morally right, does not assist us in proving that we cannot know that a
situation is morally right. If anything, thus answer choice would undermine the argument.
Answer choice (C): This is the correct answer choice. Under time duress, you could use a
mechanistic approach and select this answer simply because it is the only answer that includes the
“best consequences” idea that appeared in the conclusion.
In the absence of that approach, consider that this answer addresses the relationship we discussed
in our analysis of the stimulus (“the author makes a leap between not knowing all the consequences
and not knowing the best consequences”). In order for the author to conclude that in no situation
can we know what is morally right because morally right requires knowing the best consequences
(and we know only some of the consequences of any action), we need to show that knowing the best
consequences requires knowing all of the consequences.
Conditionally speaking, this answer is in the form a conditional relationship:
Knowing whether best consequences Knowing all consequences
The contrapositive is:
Knowing all consequences Knowing whether best consequences
Using this contrapositive, apply the Justify Formula by adding the following information from the
stimulus:
Some consequences of every action are unknown
In combination with this answer, that information establishes that:
Whether an action has the best consequences is unknown
Thus, if morally right is the same as having the best consequences, and we cannot know the best
consequences for an action, then it is true that in no situation can we know what action is morally
right.
Answer choice (D): This choice suggests that it is not necessary to know all of the consequences of
an action, which attacks the conditional conclusion rather than justifying it.
Answer choice (E): This answer suggests that an action could be determined to be morally right, and
that sentiment does not assist in justifying a conclusion that asserts that in no situation can we know
what action is morally right.
Justify the Conclusion—SN. The correct answer choice is (C)
The argument can be viewed as follows:
Premise: For each action we perform, we can know only some of its consequences.
Conclusion: Thus the view that in no situation can we know what action is morally right
would be true if an action’s being morally right were the same as the action’s
having the best consequences.
This stimulus looks somewhat intimidating, but in laymen’s terms, the argument really means the
following:
When you do something, there are some consequences that you cannot know about. So, if
being morally right is the same as knowing the best consequences, then there is no way to
know if an action is morally right.
The question asks you to Justify the Conclusion, so seek an answer that forces the conclusion
to follow from the premises. In the argument, the author makes a leap between not knowing all
the consequences and not knowing the best consequences, so you should look for an answer that
connects those two ideas (remember, morally right requires knowing the best consequences, yet we
can’t know the best consequences because we can’t know all the consequences).
Mechanistically speaking, the conclusion contains the new idea of “best consequences,” so look for
an answer that addresses that new element.
Answer choice (A): The stimulus concerns whether we can prove actions morally right, and being
able to prove some of them wrong does not help decide whether some can be proven right.
Answer choice (B): The conclusion attempts to prove that we cannot know that a situation is morally
right if morally right is the same as having the best consequences. This answer, which states that on
occasion we can know what is morally right, does not assist us in proving that we cannot know that a
situation is morally right. If anything, thus answer choice would undermine the argument.
Answer choice (C): This is the correct answer choice. Under time duress, you could use a
mechanistic approach and select this answer simply because it is the only answer that includes the
“best consequences” idea that appeared in the conclusion.
In the absence of that approach, consider that this answer addresses the relationship we discussed
in our analysis of the stimulus (“the author makes a leap between not knowing all the consequences
and not knowing the best consequences”). In order for the author to conclude that in no situation
can we know what is morally right because morally right requires knowing the best consequences
(and we know only some of the consequences of any action), we need to show that knowing the best
consequences requires knowing all of the consequences.
Conditionally speaking, this answer is in the form a conditional relationship:
Knowing whether best consequences Knowing all consequences
The contrapositive is:
Knowing all consequences Knowing whether best consequences
Using this contrapositive, apply the Justify Formula by adding the following information from the
stimulus:
Some consequences of every action are unknown
In combination with this answer, that information establishes that:
Whether an action has the best consequences is unknown
Thus, if morally right is the same as having the best consequences, and we cannot know the best
consequences for an action, then it is true that in no situation can we know what action is morally
right.
Answer choice (D): This choice suggests that it is not necessary to know all of the consequences of
an action, which attacks the conditional conclusion rather than justifying it.
Answer choice (E): This answer suggests that an action could be determined to be morally right, and
that sentiment does not assist in justifying a conclusion that asserts that in no situation can we know
what action is morally right.