- Thu Jul 17, 2014 6:18 pm
#15367
Hi Jkjones!
When looking for flaws, it's usually best to start with the conclusion and then look at how the author is trying to support that conclusion. In this case, the conclusion is "Joan and her friends have a defect in their sense of smell." The premises used to support that conclusion are that Professor Jameson, an expert on the physiology of smell, prefers a different scent to the one Joan and her friends prefer. But does that premise really support that conclusion? Does Prof. Jameson's preference really prove that there is something wrong with Joan and her friends' sense of smell?
The flaw in this argument actually is an inappropriate appeal to authority. Professor Jameson is an expert on the physiology of smell, but that doesn't mean that her preference for one smell over another proves that Joan and her friends have a defect in their sense of smell. The personal preferences of an expert don't prove some sort of defect in someone with different preferences.
Think about this parallel case: Let's say that I am an expert on the physiology of taste. If I say that I prefer the taste of beets to chocolate, would that mean that everyone who prefers the taste of chocolate over beets has a defective sense of taste?
The same reasoning applies here. Professor Jameson can tell us all about how our noses are able to detect smells, but that doesn't mean that her preferences for certain scents proves that people with different preferences have defective senses of smell.
Answer choice (D) is the correct answer here because it is the only answer choice that correctly identifies the flaw as an inappropriate appeal to authority.
Incidentally, inappropriate appeal to authority doesn't always mean that the expert appealed to has no expertise in the relevant field. Sometimes the expert appealed to might have relevant expertise, but an expert's opinion often doesn't prove anything. Experts can often have differing opinions. That's why many people might seek out a second opinion when getting diagnosed by doctors, etc.
Answer choice (B) doesn't describe a flaw in this argument. Yes, the argument does not discuss the fact that one might prefer one thing to another without liking either very much. But that distinction is not needed in this argument and so ignoring it is not a flaw of the argument.
Hope this helps!
Best,
Kelsey