- Fri Dec 30, 2011 12:00 am
#24983
Complete Question Explanation
Justify the Conclusion: The correct answer choice is (D)
This argument centers on the meaning of the promise to love “until death do us part.” The ethicist argues that if “love” refers to a feeling, then the promise makes no sense. Why? Because one does not control his or her feelings, and it does not make sense to promise something that is not under one’s control. Ultimately, the ethicist concludes that no one should take “love” in the context of marital vows to refer to feelings, i.e. that “love” should not be interpreted as a feeling.
Where did the ethicist make a logical leap? Clearly, just because promising to feel love makes no sense does not automatically prohibit us from interpreting “love” as a feeling. As a Justify the Conclusion question, we are looking to find the answer choice that, when added to the stimulus, allows the conclusion to be properly drawn. Simply put, we need to connect “promise” to “interpretation” by establishing that promises should only be interpreted in a way that makes sense.
Answer choice (A): The conclusion of this stimulus is based on a feeling we are powerless to control. The additional information that there are other feelings that we are powerless to control does not meaningfully add to the argument, and certainly does not allow us to draw the conclusion that no one should take the term “love” in marital vows to refer to feelings.
Answer choice (B): The argument in the stimulus is about how people should understand words in promises. It is not about what sorts of promises people should make in the first place. The ethicist focuses the argument on how people should interpret promises rather than on how people should make promises. This answer choice relates to how people should make promises, and thus does not actually impact the argument in the stimulus.
Answer choice (C): The ethicist seems to imply that “love” can refer to something other than a feeling. He or she does not say that it legitimately would refer to something other than a feeling. The argument is supported as long as the term “love” can refer to something other than a feeling, whether that reference is legitimate or silly.
Answer choice (D): This is the correct answer choice. When added to the stimulus, this answer choice allows the conclusion to be drawn by explaining that promises should not be interpreted in such a way that do not make sense. The stimulus already stated that the promise to love, if it refers to a feeling, would make no sense. Thus the conclusion can be properly drawn with the additional information that promises should not be interpreted in such a way that does not make sense.
Answer choice (E): The stimulus never says that the promise to love cannot be kept. Even if it does not make sense as a promise, it is still possible to keep it. If one happened to continue to feel love for the other person until death, even if he or she could not control those feelings, one still would have kept the promise.
Justify the Conclusion: The correct answer choice is (D)
This argument centers on the meaning of the promise to love “until death do us part.” The ethicist argues that if “love” refers to a feeling, then the promise makes no sense. Why? Because one does not control his or her feelings, and it does not make sense to promise something that is not under one’s control. Ultimately, the ethicist concludes that no one should take “love” in the context of marital vows to refer to feelings, i.e. that “love” should not be interpreted as a feeling.
Where did the ethicist make a logical leap? Clearly, just because promising to feel love makes no sense does not automatically prohibit us from interpreting “love” as a feeling. As a Justify the Conclusion question, we are looking to find the answer choice that, when added to the stimulus, allows the conclusion to be properly drawn. Simply put, we need to connect “promise” to “interpretation” by establishing that promises should only be interpreted in a way that makes sense.
Answer choice (A): The conclusion of this stimulus is based on a feeling we are powerless to control. The additional information that there are other feelings that we are powerless to control does not meaningfully add to the argument, and certainly does not allow us to draw the conclusion that no one should take the term “love” in marital vows to refer to feelings.
Answer choice (B): The argument in the stimulus is about how people should understand words in promises. It is not about what sorts of promises people should make in the first place. The ethicist focuses the argument on how people should interpret promises rather than on how people should make promises. This answer choice relates to how people should make promises, and thus does not actually impact the argument in the stimulus.
Answer choice (C): The ethicist seems to imply that “love” can refer to something other than a feeling. He or she does not say that it legitimately would refer to something other than a feeling. The argument is supported as long as the term “love” can refer to something other than a feeling, whether that reference is legitimate or silly.
Answer choice (D): This is the correct answer choice. When added to the stimulus, this answer choice allows the conclusion to be drawn by explaining that promises should not be interpreted in such a way that do not make sense. The stimulus already stated that the promise to love, if it refers to a feeling, would make no sense. Thus the conclusion can be properly drawn with the additional information that promises should not be interpreted in such a way that does not make sense.
Answer choice (E): The stimulus never says that the promise to love cannot be kept. Even if it does not make sense as a promise, it is still possible to keep it. If one happened to continue to feel love for the other person until death, even if he or she could not control those feelings, one still would have kept the promise.